b368f31986629584c65339d325310952.ppt
- Количество слайдов: 25
Mobile Computing Group An Introduction to Game Theory part I Vangelis Angelakis 14 / 10 / 2004
Introduction Game theory is the mathematically founded study of conflict and cooperation. Game theoretic concepts apply when the decisions/actions of independent agents affect the interests of others Agents may be individuals, groups, firms, “intelligent” devices Game theory provides them with a methodology for structuring and analyzing problems of strategic choice. By formally modeling a situation as a game requires to enumerate the players, their preferences and their strategic options, The decision maker is given a clearer and broader view of the situation in hand. TNL - Mobile Computing Group Angelakis Vangelis 14/10/2003
A little history lesson 1838: The first formal game theoretic analysis –the study of a duopoly by A. Cournot. 1921: E. Borel suggests a formal theory of games 1928: “Theory of parlour games” by von Neumann 1944: “Theory of Games and Economic behaviour” by von Neumann & O. Morgenstern –basic terminology & problem setup is standardized in this book. 1951: J. Nash proves that finite games always have an equilibrium… 1950’s-60’s: applications to war and (international) politics 1970’s: revolutionalized the economic theory, applications in sociology, psychology, evolutionary biology 1990’s: E/M spectrum auctions design 1994: Nash is awarded the Nobel prize in economics TNL - Mobile Computing Group Angelakis Vangelis 14/10/2003
Defining Games A Game is a formal model of an interactive situation The formal definition of a game declares: • The players • Their preferences • Their information • The strategic actions that are available to them • How these actions influence the outcome Games with single players are characterized decision problems Two “schools” of game theory are formed depending on the focus of games and the granularity of the game description TNL - Mobile Computing Group Angelakis Vangelis 14/10/2003
Cooperative Games A high level description declaring: -payoffs of each potential coalition that can play a game -not the formation process of the coalition Hence, it is not defined as a game in which players actually do cooperate, but as a game in which any cooperation is enforced by an outside party. This outside party involvement and the possible bargaining process that takes place do not belong to the cooperative game description. Cooperative game theory investigates coalitional games with respect to relative power held by the players and how a successful coalition should divide its gains. TNL - Mobile Computing Group Angelakis Vangelis 14/10/2003
Non-cooperative Games Players make choices of their own interest Order and timing may be crucial to determine the outcome of a game In a non-cooperative game players are unable to make enforceable contracts outside of those specifically modelled in the game. Hence, it is not defined as games in which players do not cooperate, but as games in which any cooperation must be selfenforcing. Cooperation arises, when it is in the best interest of players TNL - Mobile Computing Group Angelakis Vangelis 14/10/2003
Assumptions Strategic Behavior Being aware of your opponents existence and act trying to anticipate/counter their moves is called strategic behavior Rationality rational players always chose actions that give them an outcome they most prefer, given what their opponents will do. Predict how a game will be played or Advice how to best play in a game against rational opponents Rationality is an assumption under common knowledge Some define games as: The interaction among a group of rational agents who behave strategically TNL - Mobile Computing Group Angelakis Vangelis 14/10/2003
Strategic & Extensive Form Games Strategic form (normal form) A strategic form game can be a single round of a repeated game Time invariant (no turns) game is played in the blink of an eye List each players strategies List outcomes that result from each possible combination of moves The outcome of a game is the payoff each player gets The Payoff is a numerical value, also called Utility. Extensive form (game tree) The complete description of how a game is played as time goes by + Order of players + Information of players at each point in time More on extensive forms in part II TNL - Mobile Computing Group Angelakis Vangelis 14/10/2003
Dominance Assume a rational player having strategies A and B. If A has a higher utility than B no mater what strategic combination other players make, then strategy A is said to dominate strategy B. Rational players do not play dominated strategies. In some games examining available strategies and eliminating dominated strategies results in only one credible strategy for a rational player. TNL - Mobile Computing Group Angelakis Vangelis 14/10/2003
Prisoners’ Dilemma A bank is robbed and the robbers escape the police… A pair of suspects are arrested later in the day and are held in separate cells. Each is told that: -if one alone confesses the robbery he will be granted pardon and the other goes in prison for a long time. -if both confess then both go in prison for a short time -if both deny then both go in prison for a very short time (let’s say they will be charged only with arms possession) What action will each prisoner take? TNL - Mobile Computing Group Angelakis Vangelis 14/10/2003
Prisoners’ Dilemma II Deny Confess 2 3 I Deny 2 0 0 Confess 3 1 1 Elimination of dominated strategies TNL - Mobile Computing Group Angelakis Vangelis 14/10/2003
Prisoners’ Dilemma The individually rational outcome is worse for both players… Arms races, environmental pollution, etc are modeled by prisoners’ dilemmas… The solution to a single game is a max-min strategy, a better-play-it-safe strategy In a repeated game patterns for cooperation among the players arise (“suspects” will actually play the “deny-deny” move…) A repeated game allows for a strategy to be dependent on past moves, thus allowing for reputation effects and retribution. In infinitely repeated games, trigger strategies such as tit-for-tat encourage cooperation. TNL - Mobile Computing Group Angelakis Vangelis 14/10/2003
Quality Selection Customer Buy Don’t buy 2 1 Vo. IP Provider High 2 0 0 Low TNL - Mobile Computing Group 3 Angelakis Vangelis 1 1 14/10/2003
The Nash Equilibrium A set of strategies such that no player has incentive to unilaterally change her action. Players are in equilibrium if a change in strategies by any one of them would lead that player to earn less than if she remained with her current strategy. TNL - Mobile Computing Group Angelakis Vangelis 14/10/2003
Revisiting Quality Selection Customer Buy Don’t buy 2 1 Vo. IP Provider High 2 0 0 Low 1 3 1 1 No dominant Strategies ! – Two Nash Equilibria TNL - Mobile Computing Group Angelakis Vangelis 14/10/2003
Equilibrium selection In games with multiple Nash equilibria a theory of strategic interaction should guide players to the “most reasonable” equilibrium Large number of papers focused with equilibrium refinements that attempt to derive conditions making an equilibrium more convincing than the another. Custome r Buy Don’t buy 2 1 Vo. IP Provider High 2 Low 1 0 0 1 1 For example, in the previous game the “Highbuy” equilibrium yields higher utility for both players, so it can easily be argued that they will be self-coordinated to it. TNL - Mobile Computing Group Angelakis Vangelis 14/10/2003
Prisoners’ Dilemma Nash Equilibrium II Deny Confess 2 3 I Deny 2 0 0 Confess 3 1 1 Single Strategy combination rising from the process of dominated strategies elimination is a Nash Equilibrium TNL - Mobile Computing Group Angelakis Vangelis 14/10/2003
Mixed Strategies So far a player chose deterministically among one of her strategies. Such selections are named selections from pure strategies. Randomizing one’s choice, by selecting among her pure strategies with a certain probability is called a mixed strategy. Equilibrium is now defined by a mixed strategy for each player so that none can gain on average by unilaterally deviating. Nash proved (1951) that under mixed strategies any game in strategic-form has an equilibrium Such is therefore the game theorists recommendation in the case when an equilibrium in pure strategies does not exist. TNL - Mobile Computing Group Angelakis Vangelis 14/10/2003
Compliance Inspections II Comply Cheat 0 10 I Don’t Inspect 0 -10 0 Inspect TNL - Mobile Computing Group -1 Angelakis Vangelis -90 -6 14/10/2003
Compliance Inspections II Comply Cheat 0 10 I Don’t Inspect 0 Inspect -1 -10 0 -90 -6 Mixed strategy for I: chose Inspect with a probability. (giving a sufficient change to getting caught should deter II from choosing Cheat) • Inspect with p = 0. 01 then II receives a utility of: • 0 under Comply • 0. 99 x 10 + 0. 01 x (-90) = 9 under Cheat (has incentive to Cheat –inspection not too often) • Inspect with p = 0. 2 then II receives a utility of: • 0 under Comply • 0. 8 x 10 + 0. 2 x (-90) = -10 under Cheat (incentive to always Comply –inspections too often) TNL - Mobile Computing Group Angelakis Vangelis 14/10/2003
Compliance Inspections II Comply Cheat 0 10 I Don’t Inspect 0 Inspect -1 -10 0 -90 -6 So if player I randomizes poorly she leads player II to selecting a pure strategy. Player I must make player II indifferent to achieve equilibrium • Inspect with p = 0. 1 then II receives a utility of: • 0 under Comply • 0. 9 x 10 + 0. 1 x (-90) = 0 under Cheat Player II is rational so he knows player I will mix strategies only if I is indifferent too. How can II make I indifferent? • Cheat with p = 0. 2 then I receives a utility of: • 0. 8 x 0 + 0. 2 x (-10) = -2 under Don’t Inspect • 0. 8 x (-1) + 0. 2 x (-6) = -2 under Inspect TNL - Mobile Computing Group Angelakis Vangelis 14/10/2003
Compliance Inspections II Comply Cheat 0 10 I Don’t Inspect 0 Inspect -1 -10 0 -90 -6 Equilibrium yields an expected payoff of 0 for player II -2 for player I … Does randomizing make sense for II ? ? ? “ok, why don’t I just always chose comply since I got nothing to win anyways? ” Let’s assume player II always chooses Comply under this rationale, then I needs not randomize, just purely chose Don’t Inspect so player II’s strategy becomes sub-optimal (irrational). With no incentive to select one strategy over the other a player can mix strategies and only thus is the equilibrium reached TNL - Mobile Computing Group Angelakis Vangelis 14/10/2003
Compliance Inspections II Comply Cheat 0 10 I Don’t Inspect 0 Inspect -1 -10 0 We saw that the probabilities for mixing one’s strategies depend on opponent's payoffs… -90 -6 It could be reasoned by I that : “We just have the penalty for Cheating disgustingly high and II will be deterred to select Cheat” We saw that II’s payoffs determine the probabilities that will make I be indifferent… TNL - Mobile Computing Group Angelakis Vangelis 14/10/2003
Compliance Inspections II I Don’t Inspect Comply Cheat One could see this game as an evolutionary game: 0 -10 It is the interaction between an organization who chooses Don’t Inspect and Inspect for certain fractions 0 -90 -1 -6 of a large number of people. Player II’s actions Comply and Cheat are each chosen by a certain fraction of people involved in these interactions. 0 10 If these fractions would deviate from the equilibrium probabilities, the group whose strategies do better would increase. For example: if player I chooses Inspect too often (relative to the penalty for a cheater who is caught), the fraction of cheaters will decrease, which in turn makes Don’t Inspect a better strategy In this dynamic process, the long-term averages of the fractions approximate the equilibrium probabilities TNL - Mobile Computing Group Angelakis Vangelis 14/10/2003
TNL - Mobile Computing Group Angelakis Vangelis 14/10/2003
b368f31986629584c65339d325310952.ppt